A Totalism of His Own
David Gordon
<
BACK
Sometimes a single sentence in a
book tells you that something is radically wrong. In the present
work we find the damning statement early: "Aeschylus, Shakespeare
and Samuel Beckett are supremely great dramatists; but we cannot
rank their work in value" (p. 37). Mr. Gray uses this example to
illustrate his hobbyhorse, value pluralism; but it reveals an
astonishing failure of aesthetic judgment. How can he rank Beckett,
a minor playwright inferior to Shaw, among the "supremely great"?
What I suspect has happened is this: our author is in the grip of a
theoretical obsession. He quite properly sees that there are many
valuable types of life and deplores efforts to press people into a
common pattern. Have we not learned in the twentieth century the
dangers of totalizing ideologies? But a menace threatens that,
unless Mr. Gray can block it, will render us vulnerable to the
fanatic drive toward unity at the root of communism and fascism. If
all values could be ranked in order, would not advocates of the best
life be justified in imposing their conception of the good on those
of us less enlightened than they? It is this dire prospect that Mr.
Gray most fears, and he believes that he has the answer to it.
Suppose that important values cannot be ranked in an order of merit;
instead, they are "incommensurable," to use our author's favorite
term. Then all is well; the specter of totalitarian universalism
dissipates. No advocate of a way of life can say that his values
outrank all others, however good they seem to him. If so, will we
not all agree on a politics of toleration? How can we demand that
others fall in with our pet universal scheme, if they hold
incommensurable goods of their own? Will not a policy of modus
vivendi recommend itself instead?
Mr. Gray fails to see that his avid pursuit of pluralism conceals a
totalistic impulse of his own. So anxious is he to find plural
values that whenever any difference appears, he yells
"incommensurability" with all the monomania of Mr. Dick about King
Charles's head. Here we find the explanation of his appalling lapse
of taste. Since Beckett's plays differ in style and substance from
those of Aeschylus and Shakespeare, must they not be incommensurable
"blessed word" with them?
Our author has of course reasoned too quickly, but I do not propose
to discuss his views on the beautiful any further. Gray on the true
and the good is quite enough, and we turn at once to his ethics and
politics. The source of our author's confusion lies in pushing too
far a perfectly sound observation.
He rightly sees that we often cannot say that one value outranks
another. Is the active life of a businessman better than that of a
quiet scholar engaged in research? Should we seek constant change,
as Mrs. Virginia Postrel thinks, or adhere to customary ways, with
M.E. Bradford and the Southern Agrarians? These questions admit of
no ready answer; if so, is not Mr. Gray right in invoking the
incommensurable?
Not at all. Our cases show at most that some values cannot be rated
better or worse than various others. But why not say, then, that the
values concerned rank as roughly equal? This leaves entirely open
whether there is a highest good. Two values may count as equal, but
something else may have more value than either. Even if two values
count as about equal, values may be measured on a common scale, for
all Mr. Gray has shown otherwise. His favorite term does not apply,
as he wrongly thinks, whenever we find puzzling the relative rank of
two values.
Quite the contrary, incommensurability exists only under highly
specific circumstances, a matter Mr. Gray altogether neglects.
Suppose that I cannot say whether Shakespeare is a better poet than
Milton and cannot rank in order Shakespeare and Dante, but that I
can place Dante above Milton. Then, Shakespeare and Milton count as
incommensurable. Crucial here is the apparent anomaly: though I do
not place Dante above Shakespeare, I place Dante and not Shakespeare
above Milton. Absent this, I could not take Shakespeare and Milton
as incommensurable. Instead, I would say merely that they rank about
the same.
I have harped on what seems a technical point; but there is, I hope,
method in my madness. Our author does not grasp how difficult it is
to show that values are incommensurable; but unless he can show
clear and important instances of this phenomenon, his argument for
value pluralism collapses. To reiterate, all he has shown is that
rough equivalents in value exist. But what if something outranks
both?
We may go further. Gray's failure stems from his loose grip on what
is at stake, although this book is his second that adopts the
incommensurable as its theme. He states: "Two goods that are
incommensurable as a pair may be commensurate when either or both
are compared with other goods" (p. 41). He here falls into gross
fallacy. He does not see that one of the two incommensurable values
must be commensurable with a third, and that the other member of the
pair cannot be. In brief, Mr. Gray does not know what he is talking
about.
But I am a generous soul. Let us grant our author his key premise:
important values are incommensurable. As Mr. Gray says, "to claim
that goods are incommensurable is not to rank them. It is to say
that they cannot be ranked" (p. 41). Has he then, as he imagines,
pierced fatally the view that there is a single best form of life
for man?
You will not be surprised to learn that he has not. Even if some
forms of life are incommensurable, in the strict sense of which Mr.
Gray knows nothing, there may be a best form of life. The highest
value may outrank each incommensurable value. Suppose, e.g., with a
silliness that exceeds Mr. Gray's, that I took Shakespeare and
Milton to be incommensurable as writers, but ranked Beckett above
either. Our author s fuss and feathers about a concept best left to
the philosophy journals does not suffice to eliminate the objective
hierarchy of values that he dreads.
Our author is here not without resources: he has another fallacious
argument to throw at us. How can one speak of a best form of life?
Surely no way of life can incorporate all the virtues, since some
cannot be realized consistently with others. Think of the virtues
that animate the Iliad and those that inform the Sermon on the
Mount. . . . The lives of people exhibiting these virtues are
mutually exclusive, since each requires what the other condemns" (p.
38).
This observation, even if right, misses the point. Why must the best
form of life incorporate all possible good things? What if, say, the
life of St. Paul is better than that of Achilles, even though the
latter had virtues that the former lacked?
But even if Mr. Gray's arguments for incommensurable values fail,
must one not admire the spirit behind them? Should we not fear, as
he thinks, those who seek to impose their vision of what is best?
Once more our author relies on a false assumption. Why must a moral
view that rejects pluralism welcome coercion? I should have thought
that classical liberalism illustrates the precise contrary. In
Murray Rothbard's version of that doctrine, e.g., it is objectively
true that people ought to have a sphere of personal freedom. Why is
this position "totalistic" in a way open to objection?
I have been so absorbed in my assault on Mr. Gray that I have left
myself open to counterattack. The arguments Gray here advances in
favor of incommensurable values do not succeed; but this hardly
shows that the position is false. Many people, Isaiah Berlin not
least among them, find value pluralism appealing and right. If you
accept pluralism, must you renounce classical liberalism as
universally true?
Robert Nozick argues that you need not do so. Rights, he famously
argues, constrain us in pursuit of our goals; they are not designed
to maximize value. Thus, incommensurability of values leaves rights
unscathed. Even if some values cannot be compared, rights always
govern our conduct. Mr. Gray dissents. Appeals to rights, he argues,
do not escape the dissolving acids of incommensurability.
True enough, he says, a right does not directly aim to maximize a
value. But rights conflict with one another, and these clashes admit
of settlement only through recourse to values. And values, as Mr.
Gray has told us ad nauseam, are incommensurable. Our original
problem returns. No universally binding theory of rights can be
shown true.
As usual, Gray moves too quickly. Suppose, like Rothbard, one
contends that natural law establishes that everyone has certain
rights. How are such views overthrown by invoking incommensurable
values? Of course, many will dissent from Rothbard's theory, but
these disagreements do not demonstrate that a dispute over values
has occurred. Mr. Gray confuses disagreement, an everyday matter of
fact, with incommensurability, a highly disputable concept.
Given Mr. Gray's alarm over totalizing ideologies, it is surprising
to see how little he cares for personal freedom. People who dare to
utter the politically incorrect might not fare well in a Gray world.
"European (and American) history suggests that a society in which
racist speech is free easily becomes one in which the speech of
racial minorities is unfree. . . . These considerations tell heavily
in favour of curbs on racist speech" (p. 79). In other situations,
such muzzling may not be mandated, but "I am not convinced that
these possibilities are realistic" (p. 80).
As John Gray's readers have come to expect, the latest book contains
more than its share of mistakes. Mr. Gray says that in Nozick's
theory, side constraints "have an infinite weight when they conflict
with other values" (p. 83), despite Nozick's explicit denial that
side constraints can be thus explained. Nozick notes the suggestion
that to be bound by a side constraint is to assign violating that
constraint an infinite negative weight and says of it: "A careful
statement delimiting 'constraint views' would exclude these
gimmicky" suggestions (Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia
[New York:Basic Books, 1974], p. 29). Clausewitz's first name is
misspelled (p. 125).
From
MISES
<
BACK
|