Chapter 13: Survivals of the Non-Invidious Interests
<
BACK
In an increasing proportion as time goes on,
the anthropomorphic cult, with its code of devout observations,
suffers a progressive disintegration through the stress of economic
exigencies and the decay of the system of status. As this
disintegration proceeds, there come to be associated and blended
with the devout attitude certain other motives and impulses that are
not always of an anthropomorphic origin, nor traceable to the habit
of personal subservience. Not all of these subsidiary impulses that
blend with the habit of devoutness in the later devotional life are
altogether congruous with the devout attitude or with the
anthropomorphic apprehension of the sequence of phenomena. The
origin being not the same, their action upon the scheme of devout
life is also not in the same direction. In many ways they traverse
the underlying norm of subservience or vicarious life to which the
code of devout observations and the ecclesiastical and sacerdotal
institutions are to be traced as their substantial basis. Through
the presence of these alien motives the social and industrial regime
of status gradually disintegrates, and the canon of personal
subservience loses the support derived from an unbroken tradition.
Extraneous habits and proclivities encroach upon the field of action
occupied by this canon, and it presently comes about that the
ecclesiastical and sacerdotal structures are partially converted to
other uses, in some measure alien to the purposes of the scheme of
devout life as it stood in the days of the most vigorous and
characteristic development of the priesthood.
Among these alien motives which affect the devout scheme in its
later growth, may be mentioned the motives of charity and of social
good-fellowship, or conviviality; or, in more general terms, the
various expressions of the sense of human solidarity and sympathy.
It may be added that these extraneous uses of the ecclesiastical
structure contribute materially to its survival in name and form
even among people who may be ready to give up the substance of it. A
still more characteristic and more pervasive alien element in the
motives which have gone to formally uphold the scheme of devout life
is that non-reverent sense of aesthetic congruity with the
environment, which is left as a residue of the latter-day act of
worship after elimination of its anthropomorphic content. This has
done good service for the maintenance of the sacerdotal institution
through blending with the motive of subservience. This sense of
impulse of aesthetic congruity is not primarily of an economic
character, but it has a considerable indirect effect in shaping the
habit of mind of the individual for economic purposes in the later
stages of industrial development; its most perceptible effect in
this regard goes in the direction of mitigating the somewhat
pronounced self-regarding bias that has been transmitted by
tradition from the earlier, more competent phases of the regime of
status. The economic bearing of this impulse is therefore seen to
transverse that of the devout attitude; the former goes to qualify,
if not eliminate, the self-regarding bias, through sublation of the
antithesis or antagonism of self and not-self; while the latter,
being and expression of the sense of personal subservience and
mastery, goes to accentuate this antithesis and to insist upon the
divergence between the self-regarding interest and the interests of
the generically human life process.
This non-invidious residue of the religious life -- the sense of
communion with the environment, or with the generic life process --
as well as the impulse of charity or of sociability, act in a
pervasive way to shape men's habits of thought for the economic
purpose. But the action of all this class of proclivities is
somewhat vague, and their effects are difficult to trace in detail.
So much seems clear, however, as that the action of this entire
class of motives or aptitudes tends in a direction contrary to the
underlying principles of the institution of the leisure class as
already formulated. The basis of that institution, as well as of the
anthropomorphic cults associated with it in the cultural
development, is the habit of invidious comparison; and this habit is
incongruous with the exercise of the aptitudes now in question. The
substantial canons of the leisure-class scheme of life are a
conspicuous waste of time and substance and a withdrawal from the
industrial process; while the particular aptitudes here in question
assert themselves, on the economic side, in a deprecation of waste
and of a futile manner of life, and in an impulse to participation
in or identification with the life process, whether it be on the
economic side or in any other of its phases or aspects.
It is plain that these aptitudes and habits of life to which they
give rise where circumstances favor their expression, or where they
assert themselves in a dominant way, run counter to the
leisure-class scheme of life; but it is not clear that life under
the leisure-class scheme, as seen in the later stages of its
development, tends consistently to the repression of these aptitudes
or to exemption from the habits of thought in which they express
themselves. The positive discipline of the leisure猚lass scheme of
life goes pretty much all the other way. In its positive discipline,
by prescription and by selective elimination, the leisure-class
scheme favors the all-pervading and all-dominating primacy of the
canons of waste and invidious comparison at every conjuncture of
life. But in its negative effects the tendency of the leisure-class
discipline is not so unequivocally true to the fundamental canons of
the scheme. In its regulation of human activity for the purpose of
pecuniary decency the leisure-class canon insists on withdrawal from
the industrial process. That is to say, it inhibits activity in the
directions in which the impecunious members of the community
habitually put forth their efforts. Especially in the case of women,
and more particularly as regards the upper-class and
upper-middle-class women of advanced industrial communities, this
inhibition goes so far as to insist on withdrawal even from the
emulative process of accumulation by the quasi-predator methods of
the pecuniary occupations.
The pecuniary or the leisure-class culture, which set out as an
emulative variant of the impulse of workmanship, is in its latest
development beginning to neutralize its own ground, by eliminating
the habit of invidious comparison in respect of efficiency, or even
of pecuniary standing. On the other hand, the fact that members of
the leisure class, both men and women, are to some extent exempt
from the necessity of finding a livelihood in a competitive struggle
with their fellows, makes it possible for members of this class not
only to survive, but even, within bounds, to follow their bent in
case they are not gifted with the aptitudes which make for success
in the competitive struggle. That is to say, in the latest and
fullest development of the institution, the livelihood of members of
this class does not depend on the possession and the unremitting
exercise of those aptitudes are therefore greater in the higher
grades of the leisure class than in the general average of a
population living under the competitive system.
In an earlier chapter, in discussing the conditions of survival of
archaic traits, it has appeared that the peculiar position of the
leisure class affords exceptionally favorable chances for the
survival of traits which characterize the type of human nature
proper to an earlier and obsolete cultural stage. The class is
sheltered from the stress of economic exigencies, and is in this
sense withdrawn from the rude impact of forces which make for
adaptation to the economic situation. The survival in the leisure
class, and under the leisure-class scheme of life, of traits and
types that are reminiscent of the predatory culture has already been
discussed. These aptitudes and habits have an exceptionally
favorable chance of survival under the leisure猚lass regime. Not only
does the sheltered pecuniary position of the leisure class afford a
situation favorable to the survival of such individuals as are not
gifted with the complement of aptitudes required for serviceability
in the modern industrial process; but the leisure-class canons of
reputability at the same time enjoin the conspicuous exercise of
certain predatory aptitudes. The employments in which the predatory
aptitudes find exercise serve as an evidence of wealth, birth, and
withdrawal from the industrial process. The survival of the
predatory traits under the leisure-class culture is furthered both
negatively, through the industrial exemption of the class, and
positively, through the sanction of the leisure-class canons of
decency.
With respect to the survival of traits characteristic of the
ante-predatory savage culture the case is in some degree different.
The sheltered position of the leisure class favors the survival also
of these traits; but the exercise of the aptitudes for peace and
good-will does not have the affirmative sanction of the code of
proprieties. Individuals gifted with a temperament that is
reminiscent of the ante-predatory culture are placed at something of
an advantage within the leisure class, as compared with similarly
gifted individuals outside the class, in that they are not under a
pecuniary necessity to thwart these aptitudes that make for a
non-competitive life; but such individuals are still exposed to
something of a moral constraint which urges them to disregard these
inclinations, in that the code of proprieties enjoins upon them
habits of life based on the predatory aptitudes. So long as the
system of status remains intact, and so long as the leisure class
has other lines of non猧ndustrial activity to take to than obvious
killing of time in aimless and wasteful fatigation, so long no
considerable departure from the leisure-class scheme of reputable
life is to be looked for. The occurrence of non-predatory
temperament with the class at that stage is to be looked upon as a
case of sporadic reversion. But the reputable non-industrial outlets
for the human propensity to action presently fail, through the
advance of economic development, the disappearance of large game,
the decline of war, the obsolescence of proprietary government, and
the decay of the priestly office. When this happens, the situation
begins to change. Human life must seek expression in one direction
if it may not in another; and if the predatory outlet fails, relief
is sought elsewhere.
As indicated above, the exemption from pecuniary stress has been
carried farther in the case of the leisure-class women of the
advanced industrial communities than in that of any other
considerable group of persons. The women may therefore be expected
to show a more pronounced reversion to a non-invidious temperament
than the men. But there is also among men of the leisure class a
perceptible increase in the range and scope of activities that
proceed from aptitudes which are not to be classed as
self-regarding, and the end of which is not an invidious
distinction. So, for instance, the greater number of men who have to
do with industry in the way of pecuniarily managing an enterprise
take some interest and some pride in seeing that the work is well
done and is industrially effective, and this even apart from the
profit which may result from any improvement of this kind. The
efforts of commercial clubs and manufacturers' organizations in this
direction of non-invidious advancement of industrial efficiency are
also well know.
The tendency to some other than an invidious purpose in life has
worked out in a multitude of organizations, the purpose of which is
some work of charity or of social amelioration. These organizations
are often of a quasi-religious or pseudo-religious character, and
are participated in by both men and women. Examples will present
themselves in abundance on reflection, but for the purpose of
indicating the range of the propensities in question and of
characterizing them, some of the more obvious concrete cases may be
cited. Such, for instance, are the agitation for temperance and
similar social reforms, for prison reform, for the spread of
education, for the suppression of vice, and for the avoidance of war
by arbitration, disarmament, or other means; such are, in some
measure, university settlements, neighborhood guilds, the various
organizations typified by the Young Men's Christian Association and
Young People's Society for Christian Endeavor, sewing-clubs, art
clubs, and even commercial clubs; such are also, in some slight
measure, the pecuniary foundations of semi-public establishments for
charity, education, or amusement, whether they are endowed by
wealthy individuals or by contributions collected from persons of
smaller means -- in so far as these establishments are not of a
religious character.
It is of course not intended to say that these efforts proceed
entirely from other motives than those of a self猺egarding kind. What
can be claimed is that other motives are present in the common run
of cases, and that the perceptibly greater prevalence of effort of
this kind under the circumstances of the modern industrial life than
under the unbroken regime of the principle of status, indicates the
presence in modern life of an effective scepticism with respect to
the full legitimacy of an emulative scheme of life. It is a matter
of sufficient notoriety to have become a commonplace jest that
extraneous motives are commonly present among the incentives to this
class of work -- motives of a self-regarding kind, and especially
the motive of an invidious distinction. To such an extent is this
true, that many ostensible works of disinterested public spirit are
no doubt initiated and carried on with a view primarily to the
enhance repute or even to the pecuniary gain, of their promoters. In
the case of some considerable groups of organizations or
establishments of this kind the invidious motive is apparently the
dominant motive both with the initiators of the work and with their
supporters. This last remark would hold true especially with respect
to such works as lend distinction to their doer through large and
conspicuous expenditure; as, for example, the foundation of a
university or of a public library or museum; but it is also, and
perhaps equally, true of the more commonplace work of participation
in such organizations. These serve to authenticate the pecuniary
reputability of their members, as well as gratefully to keep them in
mind of their superior status by pointing the contrast between
themselves and the lower-lying humanity in whom the work of
amelioration is to be wrought; as, for example, the university
settlement, which now has some vogue. But after all allowances and
deductions have been made, there is left some remainder of motives
of a non-emulative kind. The fact itself that distinction or a
decent good fame is sought by this method is evidence of a prevalent
sense of the legitimacy , and of the presumptive effectual presence,
of a non-emulative, non-invidious interest, as a consistent factor
in the habits of thought of modern communities.
In all this latter-day range of leisure-class activities that
proceed on the basis of a non-invidious and non-religious interest,
it is to be noted that the women participate more actively and more
persistently than the men -- except, of course, in the case of such
works as require a large expenditure of means. The dependent
pecuniary position of the women disables them for work requiring
large expenditure. As regards the general range of ameliorative
work, the members of the priesthood or clergy of the less naively
devout sects, or the secularized denominations, are associated with
the class of women. This is as the theory would have it. In other
economic relations, also, this clergy stands in a somewhat equivocal
position between the class of women and that of the men engaged in
economic pursuits. By tradition and by the prevalent sense of the
proprieties, both the clergy and the women of the well-to-do classes
are placed in the position of a vicarious leisure class; with both
classes the characteristic relation which goes to form the habits of
thought of the class is a relation of subservience -- that is to
say, an economic relation conceived in personal terms; in both
classes there is consequently perceptible a special proneness to
construe phenomena in terms of personal relation rather than of
causal sequence; both classes are so inhibited by the canons of
decency from the ceremonially unclean processes of the lucrative or
productive occupations as to make participation in the industrial
life process of today a moral impossibility for them. The result of
this ceremonial exclusion from productive effort of the vulgar sort
is to draft a relatively large share of the energies of the modern
feminine and priestly classes into the service of other interests
than the self-regarding one. The code leaves no alternative
direction in which the impulse to purposeful action may find
expression. The effect of a consistent inhibition on industrially
useful activity in the case of the leisure-class women shows itself
in a restless assertion of the impulse to workmanship in other
directions than that of business activity.
As has been noticed already, the everyday life of the well-to-do
women and the clergy contains a larger element of status than that
of the average of the men, especially than that of the men engaged
in the modern industrial occupations proper. Hence the devout
attitude survives in a better state of preservation among these
classes than among the common run of men in the modern communities.
Hence an appreciable share of the energy which seeks expression in a
non-lucrative employment among these members of the vicarious
leisure classes may be expected to eventuate in devout observances
and works of piety. Hence, in part, the excess of the devout
proclivity in women, spoken of in the last chapter. But it is more
to the present point to note the effect of this proclivity in
shaping the action and coloring the purposes of the non-lucrative
movements and organizations here under discussion. Where this devout
coloring is present it lowers the immediate efficiency of the
organizations for any economic end to which their efforts may be
directed. Many organizations, charitable and ameliorative, divide
their attention between the devotional and the secular well-being of
the people whose interests they aim to further. It can scarcely he
doubted that if they were to give an equally serious attention and
effort undividedly to the secular interests of these people, the
immediate economic value of their work should be appreciably higher
than it is. It might of course similarly be said, if this were the
place to say it, that the immediate efficiency of these works of
amelioration for the devout might be greater if it were not hampered
with the secular motives and aims which are usually present.
Some deduction is to be made from the economic value of this class
of non-invidious enterprise, on account of the intrusion of the
devotional interest. But there are also deductions to be made on
account of the presence of other alien motives which more or less
broadly traverse the economic trend of this non-emulative expression
of the instinct of workmanship. To such an extent is this seen to be
true on a closer scrutiny, that, when all is told, it may even
appear that this general class of enterprises is of an altogether
dubious economic value -- as measured in terms of the fullness or
facility of life of the individuals or classes to whose amelioration
the enterprise is directed. For instance, many of the efforts now in
reputable vogue for the amelioration of the indigent population of
large cities are of the nature, in great part, of a mission of
culture. It is by this means sought to accelerate the rate of speed
at which given elements of the upper-class culture find acceptance
in the everyday scheme of life of the lower classes. The solicitude
of "settlements," for example, is in part directed to enhance the
industrial efficiency of the poor and to teach them the more
adequate utilization of the means at hand; but it is also no less
consistently directed to the inculcation, by precept and example, of
certain punctilios of upper-class propriety in manners and customs.
The economic substance of these proprieties will commonly be found
on scrutiny to be a conspicuous waste of time and goods. Those good
people who go out to humanize the poor are commonly, and advisedly,
extremely scrupulous and silently insistent in matters of decorum
and the decencies of life. They are commonly persons of an exemplary
life and gifted with a tenacious insistence on ceremonial cleanness
in the various items of their daily consumption. The cultural or
civilizing efficacy of this inculcation of correct habits of thought
with respect to the consumption of time and commodities is scarcely
to be overrated; nor is its economic value to the individual who
acquires these higher and more reputable ideals inconsiderable.
Under the circumstances of the existing pecuniary culture, the
reputability, and consequently the success, of the individual is in
great measure dependent on his proficiency in demeanor and methods
of consumption that argue habitual waste of time and goods. But as
regards the ulterior economic bearing of this training in worthier
methods of life, it is to be said that the effect wrought is in
large part a substitution of costlier or less efficient methods of
accomplishing the same material results, in relations where the
material result is the fact of substantial economic value. The
propaganda of culture is in great part an inculcation of new tastes,
or rather of a new schedule of proprieties, which have been adapted
to the upper-class scheme of life under the guidance of the
leisure-class formulation of the principles of status and pecuniary
decency. This new schedule of proprieties is intruded into the
lower-class scheme of life from the code elaborated by an element of
the population whose life lies outside the industrial process; and
this intrusive schedule can scarcely be expected to fit the
exigencies of life for these lower classes more adequately than the
schedule already in vogue among them, and especially not more
adequately than the schedule which they are themselves working out
under the stress of modern industrial life.
All this of course does not question the fact that the prOprieties
of the substituted schedule are more decorous than those which they
displace. The doubt which presents itself is simply a doubt as to
the economic expediency of this work of regeneration -- that is to
say, the economic expediency in that immediate and material bearing
in which the effects of the change can be ascertained with some
degree of confidence, and as viewed from the standpoint not of the
individual but of the facility of life of the collectivity. For an
appreciation of the economic expediency of these enterprises of
amelioration, therefore, their effective work is scarcely to be
taken at its face value, even where the aim of the enterprise is
primarily an economic one and where the interest on which it
proceeds is in no sense self-regarding or invidious. The economic
reform wrought is largely of the nature of a permutation in the
methods of conspicuous waste.
But something further is to be said with respect to the character of
the disinterested motives and canons of procedure in all work of
this class that is affected by the habits of thought characteristic
of the pecuniary culture; and this further consideration may lead to
a further qualification of the conclusions already reached. As has
been seen in an earlier chapter, the canons of reputability or
decency under the pecuniary culture insist on habitual futility of
effort as the mark of a pecuniarily blameless life. There results
not only a habit of disesteem of useful occupations, but there
results also what is of more decisive consequence in guiding the
action of any organized body of people that lays claim to social
good repute. There is a tradition which requires that one should not
be vulgarly familiar with any of the processes or details that have
to do with the material necessities of life. One may meritoriously
show a quantitative interest in the well-being of the vulgar,
through subscriptions or through work on managing committees and the
like. One may, perhaps even more meritoriously, show solicitude in
general and in detail for the cultural welfare of the vulgar, in the
way of contrivances for elevating their tastes and affording them
opportunities for spiritual amelioration. But one should not betray
an intimate knowledge of the material circumstances of vulgar life,
or of the habits of thought of the vulgar classes, such as would
effectually direct the efforts of these organizations to a
materially useful end. This reluctance to avow an unduly intimate
knowledge of the lower-class conditions of life in detail of course
prevails in very different degrees in different individuals; but
there is commonly enough of it present collectively in any
organization of the kind in question profoundly to influence its
course of action. By its cumulative action in shaping the usage and
precedents of any such body, this shrinking from an imputation of
unseemly familiarity with vulgar life tends gradually to set aside
the initial motives of the enterprise, in favor of certain guiding
principles of good repute, ultimately reducible to terms of
pecuniary merit. So that in an organization of long standing the
initial motive of furthering the facility of life in these classes
comes gradually to be an ostensible motive only, and the vulgarly
effective work of the organization tends to obsolescence.
What is true of the efficiency of organizations for non-invidious
work in this respect is true also as regards the work of individuals
proceeding on the same motives; though it perhaps holds true with
more qualification for individuals than for organized enterprises.
The habit of gauging merit by the leisure-class canons of wasteful
expenditure and unfamiliarity with vulgar life, whether on the side
of production or of consumption, is necessarily strong in the
individuals who aspire to do some work of public utility. And if the
individual should forget his station and turn his efforts to vulgar
effectiveness, the common sense of the community-the sense of
pecuniary decency -- would presently reject his work and set him
right. An example of this is seen in the administration of bequests
made by public-spirited men for the single purpose (at least
ostensibly) of furthering the facility of human life in some
particular respect. The objects for which bequests of this class are
most frequently made at present are most frequently made at present
are schools, libraries, hospitals, and asylums for the infirm or
unfortunate. The avowed purpose of the donor in these cases is the
amelioration of human life in the particular respect which is named
in the bequest; but it will be found an invariable rule that in the
execution of the work not a little of other motives, frequenCy
incompatible with the initial motive, is present and determines the
particular disposition eventually made of a good share of the means
which have been set apart by the bequest. Certain funds, for
instance, may have been set apart as a foundation for a foundling
asylum or a retreat for invalids. The diversion of expenditure to
honorific waste in such cases is not uncommon enough to cause
surprise or even to raise a smile. An appreciable share of the funds
is spent in the construction of an edifice faced with some
aesthetically objectionable but expensive stone, covered with
grotesque and incongruous details, and designed, in its battlemented
walls and turrets and its massive portals and strategic approaches,
to suggest certain barbaric methods of warfare. The interior of the
structure shows the same pervasive guidance of the canons of
conspicuous waste and predatory exploit. The windows, for instance,
to go no farther into detail, are placed with a view to impress
their pecuniary excellence upon the chance beholder from the
outside, rather than with a view to effectiveness for their
ostensible end in the convenience or comfort of the beneficiaries
within; and the detail of interior arrangement is required to
conform itself as best it may to this alien but imperious
requirement of pecuniary beauty.
In all this, of course, it is not to he presumed that the donor
would have found fault, or that he would have done otherwise if he
had taken control in person; it appears that in those cases where
such a personal direction is exercised -- where the enterprise is
conducted by direct expenditure and superintendence instead of by
bequest -- the aims and methods of management are not different in
this respect. Nor would the beneficiaries, or the outside observers
whose ease or vanity are not immediately touched, be pleased with a
different disposition of the funds. It would suit no one to have the
enterprise conducted with a view directly to the most economical and
effective use of the means at hand for the initial, material end of
the foundation. All concerned, whether their interest is immediate
and self-regarding, or contemplative only, agree that some
considerable share of the expenditure should go to the higher or
spiritual needs derived from the habit of an invidious comparison in
predatory exploit and pecuniary waste. But this only goes to say
that the canons of emulative and pecuniary reputability so far
pervade the common sense of the community as to permit no escape or
evasion, even in the case of an enterprise which ostensibly proceeds
entirely on the basis of a non-invidious interest.
It may even be that the enterprise owes its honorific virtue, as a
means of enhancing the donor's good repute, to the imputed presence
of this non-invidious motive; but that does not hinder the invidious
interest from guiding the expenditure. The effectual presence of
motives of an emulative or invidious origin in non-emulative works
of this kind might be shown at length and with detail, in any one of
the classes of enterprise spoken of above. Where these honorific
details occur, in such cases, they commonly masquerade under
designations that belong in the field of the aesthetic, ethical or
economic interest. These special motives, derived from the standards
and canons of the pecuniary culture, act surreptitiously to divert
effort of a non-invidious kind from effective service, without
disturbing the agent's sense of good intention or obtruding upon his
consciousness the substantial futility of his work. Their effect
might be traced through the entire range of that schedule of
non-invidious, meliorative enterprise that is so considerable a
feature, and especially so conspicuous a feature, in the overt
scheme of life of the well-to-do. But the theoretical bearing is
perhaps clear enough and may require no further illustration;
especially as some detailed attention will be given to one of these
lines of enterprise -- the establishments for the higher learning --
in another connection.
Under the circumstances of the sheltered situation in which the
leisure class is placed there seems, therefore, to be something of a
reversion to the range of non-invidious impulses that characterizes
the ante-predatory savage culture. The reversion comprises both the
sense of workmanship and the proclivity to indolence and
good-fellowship. But in the modern scheme of life canons of conduct
based on pecuniary or invidious merit stand in the way of a free
exercise of these impulses; and the dominant presence of these
canons of conduct goes far to divert such efforts as are made on the
basis of the non-invidious interest to the service of that invidious
interest on which the pecuniary culture rests. The canons of
pecuniary decency are reducible for the present purpose to the
principles of waste, futility, and ferocity. The requirements of
decency are imperiously present in meliorative enterprise as in
other lines of conduct, and exercise a selective surveillance over
the details of conduct and management in any enterprise. By guiding
and adapting the method in detail, these canons of decency go far to
make all non-invidious aspiration or effort nugatory. The pervasive,
impersonal, un-eager principle of futility is at hand from day to
day and works obstructively to hinder the effectual expression of so
much of the surviving ante-predatory aptitudes as is to be classed
under the instinct of workmanship; but its presence does not
preclude the transmission of those aptitudes or the continued
recurrence of an impulse to find expression for them.
In the later and farther development of the pecuniary culture, the
requirement of withdrawal from the industrial process in order to
avoid social odium is carried so far as to comprise abstention from
the emulative employments. At this advanced stage the pecuniary
culture negatively favors the assertion of the non-invidious
propensities by relaxing the stress laid on the merit of emulative,
predatory , or pecuniary occupations, as compared with those of an
industrial or productive kind. As was noticed above, the requirement
of such withdrawal from all employment that is of human use applies
more rigorously to the upper-class women than to any other class,
unless the priesthood of certain cults might be cited as an
exception, perhaps more apparent than real, to this rule. The reason
for the more extreme insistence on a futile life for this class of
women than for the men of the same pecuniary and social grade lies
in their being not only an upper-grade leisure class but also at the
same time a vicarious leisure class. There is in their case a double
ground for a consistent withdrawal from useful effort.
It has been well and repeatedly said by popular writers and speakers
who reflect the common sense of intelligent people on questions of
social structure and function that the position of woman in any
community is the most striking index of the level of culture
attained by the community, and it might be added, by any given class
in the community. This remark is perhaps truer as regards the stage
of economic development than as regards development in any other
respect. At the same time the position assigned to the woman in the
accepted scheme of life, in any community or under any culture, is
in a very great degree an expression of traditions which have been
shaped by the circumstances of an earlier phase of development, and
which have been but partially adapted to the existing economic
circumstances, or to the existing exigencies of temperament and
habits of mind by which the women living under this modern economic
situation are actuated.
The fact has already been remarked upon incidentally in the course
of the discussion of the growth of economic institutions generally,
and in particular in speaking of vicarious leisure and of dress,
that the position of women in the modern economic scheme is more
widely and more consistently at variance with the promptings of the
instinct of workmanship than is the position of the men of the same
classes. It is also apparently true that the woman's temperament
includes a larger share of this instinct that approves peace and
disapproves futility. It is therefore not a fortuitous circumstance
that the women of modern industrial communities show a livelier
sense of the discrepancy between the accepted scheme of life and the
exigencies of the economic situation.
The several phases of the "woman question" have brought out in
intelligible form the extent to which the life of women in modern
society, and in the polite circles especially, is regulated by a
body of common sense formulated under the economic circumstances of
an earlier phase of development. It is still felt that woman's life,
in its civil, economic, and social bearing, is essentially and
normally a vicarious life, the merit or demerit of which is, in the
nature of things, to be imputed to some other individual who stands
in some relation of ownership or tutelage to the woman. So, for
instance, any action on the part of a woman which traverses an
injunction of the accepted schedule of proprieties is felt to
reflect immediately upon the honor of the man whose woman she is.
There may of course be some sense of incongruity in the mind of any
one passing an opinion of this kind on the woman's frailty or
perversity; but the common-sense judgment of the community in such
matters is, after all, delivered without much hesitation, and few
men would question the legitimacy of their sense of an outraged
tutelage in any case that might arise. On the other hand, relatively
little discredit attaches to a woman through the evil deeds of the
man with whom her life is associated.
The good and beautiful scheme of life, then -- that is to say the
scheme to which we are habituated -- assigns to the woman a "sphere"
ancillary to the activity of the man; and it is felt that any
departure from the traditions of her assigned round of duties is
unwomanly. If the question is as to civil rights or the suffrage,
our common sense in the matter -- that is to say the logical
deliverance of our general scheme of life upon the point in question
-- says that the woman should be represented in the body politic and
before the law, not immediately in her own person, but through the
mediation of the head of the household to which she belongs. It is
unfeminine in her to aspire to a self-directing, self-centered life;
and our common sense tells us that her direct participation in the
affairs of the community, civil or industrial, is a menace to that
social order which expresses our habits of thought as they have been
formed under the guidance of the traditions of the pecuniary
culture. "All this fume and froth of 'emancipating woman from the
slavery of man' and so on, is, to use the chaste and expressive
language of Elizabeth Cady Stanton inversely, 'utter rot.' The
social relations of the sexes are fixed by nature. Our entire
civilization -- that is whatever is good in it -- is based on the
home." The "home" is the household with a male head. This view, but
commonly expressed even more chastely, is the prevailing view of the
woman's status, not only among the common run of the men of
civilized communities, but among the women as well. Women have a
very alert sense of what the scheme of proprieties requires, and
while it is true that many of them are ill at ease under the details
which the code imposes, there are few who do not recognize that the
existing moral order, of necessity and by the divine right of
prescription, places the woman in a position ancillary to the man.
In the last analysis, according to her own sense of what is good and
beautiful, the woman's life is, and in theory must be, an expression
of the man's life at the second remove.
But in spite of this pervading sense of what is the good and natural
place for the woman, there is also perceptible an incipient
development of sentiment to the effect that this whole arrangement
of tutelage and vicarious life and imputation of merit and demerit
is somehow a mistake. Or, at least, that even if it may be a natural
growth and a good arrangement in its time and place, and in spite of
its patent aesthetic value, still it does not adequately serve the
more everyday ends of life in a modern industrial community. Even
that large and substantial body of well-bred, upper and middle-class
women to whose dispassionate, matronly sense of the traditional
proprieties this relation of status commends itself as fundamentally
and eternally right-even these, whose attitude is conservative,
commonly find some slight discrepancy in detail between things as
they are and things as they should be in this respect. But that less
manageable body of modern women who, by force of youth, education,
or temperament, are in some degree out of touch with the traditions
of status received from the barbarian culture, and in whom there is,
perhaps, an undue reversion to the impulse of self-expression and
workmanship -- these are touched with a sense of grievance too vivid
to leave them at rest.
In this "New-Woman" movement -- as these blind and incoherent
efforts to rehabilitate the woman's pre-glacial standing have been
named -- there are at least two elements discernible, both of which
are of an economic character. These two elements or motives are
expressed by the double watchword, "Emancipation" and "Work." Each
of these words is recognized to stand for something in the way of a
wide-spread sense of grievance. The prevalence of the sentiment is
recognized even by people who do not see that there is any real
ground for a grievance in the situation as it stands today. It is
among the women of the well-to-do classes, in the communities which
are farthest advanced in industrial development, that this sense of
a grievance to be redressed is most alive and finds most frequent
expression. That is to say, in other words, there is a demand, more
or less serious, for emancipation from all relation of status,
tutelage, or vicarious life; and the revulsion asserts itself
especially among the class of women upon whom the scheme of life
handed down from the regime of status imposes with least litigation
a vicarious life, and in those communities whose economic
development has departed farthest from the circumstances to which
this traditional scheme is adapted. The demand comes from that
portion of womankind which is excluded by the canons of good repute
from all effectual work, and which is closely reserved for a life of
leisure and conspicuous consumption.
More than one critic of this new-woman movement has misapprehended
its motive. The case of the American "new woman" has lately been
summed up with some warmth by a popular observer of social
phenomena: "She is petted by her husband, the most devoted and
hard-working of husbands in the world. ... She is the superior of
her husband in education, and in almost every respect. She is
surrounded by the most numerous and delicate attentions. Yet she is
not satisfied. ... The Anglo-Saxon 'new woman' is the most
ridiculous production of modern times, and destined to be the most
ghastly failure of the century." Apart from the deprecation --
perhaps well placed -- which is contained in this presentment, it
adds nothing but obscurity to the woman question. The grievance of
the new woman is made up of those things which this typical
characterization of the movement urges as reasons why she should be
content. She is petted, and is permitted, or even required, to
consume largely and conspicuously -- vicariously for her husband or
other natural guardian. She is exempted, or debarred, from vulgarly
useful employment -- in order to perform leisure vicariously for the
good repute of her natural (pecuniary) guardian. These offices are
the conventional marks of the un-free, at the same time that they
are incompatible with the human impulse to purposeful activity. But
the woman is endowed with her share-which there is reason to believe
is more than an even share -- of the instinct of workmanship, to
which futility of life or of expenditure is obnoxious. She must
unfold her life activity in response to the direct, unmediated
stimuli of the economic environment with which she is in contact.
The impulse is perhaps stronger upon the woman than upon the man to
live her own life in her own way and to enter the industrial process
of the community at something nearer than the second remove.
So long as the woman's place is consistently that of a drudge, she
is, in the average of cases, fairly contented with her lot. She not
only has something tangible and purposeful to do, but she has also
no time or thought to spare for a rebellious assertion of such human
propensity to self-direction as she has inherited. And after the
stage of universal female drudgery is passed, and a vicarious
leisure without strenuous application becomes the accredited
employment of the women of the well-to-do classes, the prescriptive
force of the canon of pecuniary decency, which requires the
observance of ceremonial futility on their part, will long preserve
high-minded women from any sentimental leaning to self-direction and
a "sphere of usefulness." This is especially true during the earlier
phases of the pecuniary culture, while the leisure of the leisure
class is still in great measure a predatory activity, an active
assertion of mastery in which there is enough of tangible purpose of
an invidious kind to admit of its being taken seriously as an
employment to which one may without shame put one's hand. This
condition of things has obviously lasted well down into the present
in some communities. It continues to hold to a different extent for
different individuals, varying with the vividness of the sense of
status and with the feebleness of the impulse to workmanship with
which the individual is endowed. But where the economic structure of
the community has so far outgrown the scheme of life based on status
that the relation of personal subservience is no longer felt to be
the sole "natural" human relation; there the ancient habit of
purposeful activity will begin to assert itself in the less
conformable individuals against the more recent, relatively
superficial, relatively ephemeral habits and views which the
predatory and the pecuniary culture have contributed to our scheme
of life. These habits and views begin to lose their coercive force
for the community or the class in question so soon as the habit of
mind and the views of life due to the predatory and the
quasi-peaceable discipline cease to be in fairly close accord with
the later-developed economic situation. This is evident in the case
of the industrious classes of modern communities; for them the
leisure-class scheme of life has lost much of its binding force,
especially as regards the element of status. But it is also visibly
being verified in the case of the upper classes, though not in the
same manner.
The habits derived from the predatory and quasi-peaceable culture
are relatively ephemeral variants of certain underlying propensities
and mental characteristics of the race; which it owes to the
protracted discipline of the earlier, proto-anthropoid cultural
stage of peaceable, relatively undifferentiated economic life
carried on in contact with a relatively simple and invariable
material environment. When the habits superinduced by the emulative
method of life have ceased to enjoy the section of existing economic
exigencies, a process of disintegration sets in whereby the habits
of thought of more recent growth and of a less generic character to
some extent yield the ground before the more ancient and more
pervading spiritual characteristics of the race.
In a sense, then, the new-woman movement marks a reversion to a more
generic type of human character, or to a less differentiated
expression of human nature. It is a type of human nature which is to
be characterized as proto-anthropoid, and, as regards the substance
if not the form of its dominant traits, it belongs to a cultural
stage that may be classed as possibly sub-human. The particular
movement or evolutional feature in question of course shares this
characterization with the rest of the later social development, in
so far as this social development shows evidence of a reversion to
the spiritual attitude that characterizes the earlier,
undifferentiated stage of economic revolution. Such evidence of a
general tendency to reversion from the dominance of the invidious
interest is not entirely wanting, although it is neither plentiful
nor unquestionably convincing. The general decay of the sense of
status in modern industrial communities goes some way as evidence in
this direction; and the perceptible return to a disapproval of
futility in human life, and a disapproval of such activities as
serve only the individual gain at the cost of the collectivity or at
the cost of other social groups, is evidence to a like effect. There
is a perceptible tendency to deprecate the infliction of pain, as
well as to discredit all marauding enterprises, even where these
expressions of the invidious interest do not tangibly work to the
material detriment of the community or of the individual who passes
an opinion on them. It may even be said that in the modern
industrial communities the average, dispassionate sense of men says
that the ideal character is a character which makes for peace,
good-will, and economic efficiency, rather than for a life of
self-seeking, force, fraud, and mastery.
The influence of the leisure class is not consistently for or
against the rehabilitation of this proto-anthropoid human nature. So
far as concerns the chance of survival of individuals endowed with
an exceptionally large share of the primitive traits, the sheltered
position of the class favors its members directly by withdrawing
them from the pecuniary struggle; but indirectly, through the
leisure-class canons of conspicuous waste of goods and effort, the
institution of a leisure class lessens the chance of survival of
such individuals in the entire body of the population. The decent
requirements of waste absorb the surplus energy of the population in
an invidious struggle and leave no margin for the non-invidious
expression of life. The remoter, less tangible, spiritual effects of
the discipline of decency go in the same direction and work perhaps
more effectually to the same end. The canons of decent life are an
elaboration of the principle of invidious comparison, and they
accordingly act consistently to inhibit all non-invidious effort and
to inculcate the self-regarding attitude.
<
BACK
|